This blogpost is written by Alexander Edlich and Alfred Archer, writing about their recent paper in Social Epistemology entitled 'Rejecting Identities: Stigma and Hermeneutical Injustice'.
To seek, and accept, medical help, it is
often necessary to realize that one needs it. Sometimes, however, people refuse
to accept they need help, and this disables them from accessing medical
resources. This refusal need not be due to stubbornness but can be the result
of unjust social factors. In particular, we suggest that stigma can unjustly
prevent people from making sense of their situation, including stigmatized
illnesses.
Take, for instance, the American writer Caroline Knapp’s account of
her struggle to accept the idea that she was an alcoholic in her memoir Drinking:
A Love Story. She describes how at times she was so drunk that she
would ‘drive home with one eye shut, to avoid double vision’ (p. 54).
After
being advised by her therapist that she should stop drinking, she decided to
attend an Alcoholics Anonymous meeting. Once in the meeting though, she felt a
strong revulsion to accepting that she belonged there. As she describes it, she
“looked around at the dingy room with the old men sipping coffee from foam cups
and I thought, No way. No way in hell I’m doing this. This is not me. I
do not belong here’ (pp. 190–191).
For Knapp to accept that she was an
alcoholic would mean ‘owning up to flaws and imperfections and depths of
confusion I was too ashamed to reveal’. This shame that she felt about her
alcoholism was a response to the social stigma attached to it. Even when she
had accepted her alcoholism and stopped drinking, Knapp continued to be very
careful about which people she would discuss it with ‘for fear of being judged’
(p. 244).
What prevented Knapp first from accepting and even longer from
communicating about her situation was the stigma attached to alcoholism, and
thus a social factor burdening those suffering from it. This made it harder for her to seek help.
|
The cover of Knapp's book |
Knapp is far from alone in struggling with
this, the stigma attached to alcoholism is a significant barrier to people
seeking out medical assistance. This difficulty in accepting one’s addiction is
a major problem, given that this acceptance is crucial for overcoming the
addiction and also for seeking help in the first place.
While medical professionals are aware of
the importance of reducing the stigma attached to medical conditions like addiction,
the impact of stigma on self-understanding is not only practical, but, we
argue, also creates a particular type of hermeneutical injustice: those whose
experiences are stigmatized are unjustly made to reject helpful descriptions of
their situation.
Hermeneutical injustice is the label
philosophers use, coined by Miranda Fricker, to describe cases where the social
practices of knowing, learning, and communicating are unjust so that persons in
particular social positions are deprived of the means to make sense of their
experiences. In paradigmatic cases, this occurs because dominant discourses do
not include concepts that are needed to make sense of the experiences of
marginally situated agents.
For example,
Fricker argues that before the development of the concept ‘sexual harassment’
people who experienced unwanted sexual attention in the workplace were not able
to properly name their experiences. In this case, they were unfairly prevented
from fully understanding the situation they were in because they lacked the
concepts needed to articulate what it is they were experiencing, which,
consequently, also disabled them from sharing their experiences.
The stigma related to addiction (and other
stigmatized experiences, like homosexuality or suffering intimate partner
violence) also unfairly prevents people from making sense of their experiences
but does so in a subtly different way. Here the conceptual resources are
available to people. The concept of an alcoholic or an addict was available to
Knapp and once she accepted that it applied to her, she was able to access the
resources she needed to manage her addiction, including a supportive community
of people struggling with the same problem.
What prevented Knapp from accessing
these resources was not the absence of a concept but the stigma that was
attached to it. Knapp denied herself access to the hermeneutic resources that
go with the label ‘alcoholic’ because of the stigma attached to this identity,
which led her to refuse to accept that the label applied to her. In this way,
stigma can unjustly cause people to reject helpful descriptions of their
situation or identity.
To come to terms with a condition like
addiction and to seek help about it, it is important to understand one’s
situation and to accept it. Some people refuse such acceptance, and they can
suffer gravely from it. This is a problem for medical practice, but,
importantly, it can also be a problem of justice: to offer help, but also to
treat people justly, we must make sure that stigma does not stand in the way of
self-understanding.
Alexander Edlich completed his PhD at Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität Munich in 2023, where he then was a postdoctoral researcher. He works on moral responsibility (specifically blame, protest, and apology), the philosophy of emotions, and feminist and LGBTQ ethics.
Alfred Archer is Associate Professor of Philosophy at Tilburg University. He is interested in ethics, social philosophy, philosophy of sport, and moral psychology. He is the co-author of Honouring and Admiring the Immoral: An Ethical Guide (Routledge 2021), Why It’s OK to be a Sports Fan (Routledge 2024) and Extravagance and Misery: The Emotional Regime of Market Societies (OUP 2024).