Before the development and adoption of the DSM-III in 1980, psychiatry’s disciplinary status was arguably precarious. The likelihood of two psychiatrists agreeing on a diagnosis was little better than chance, and the antipsychiatry movement had raised serious criticisms of its methods and categories. This was unacceptable not only for psychiatry as a discipline but also for patients, who could receive arbitrary diagnoses depending on the individual clinician’s perspective and thus miss out on appropriate treatment.
Given such a high value and standardized conception of objectivity, some clinicians may lack either the skills or the will to engage with information that falls outside the standard (and is thus deemed “subjective”), to take up or engage with patients’ conceptual resources and interpretations, and more broadly, to treat patients as epistemic agents seeking self-understanding.
Others, of course, do have both the skills and the will. But what must be emphasized is the structural dimension of the issue: beyond individual clinicians’ attitudes lies a fundamental conception — that of objectivity — which underpins psychiatric theory and practice, and which systematically hinders engagement with patients as epistemic agents, instead promoting their treatment as mere informants or sources of information.
![]() |
"[I]f psychiatry is to be an epistemically just discipline, it must also find ways to engage with patients as epistemic agents." |
I am not arguing that psychiatry should abandon the pursuit of objectivity or that generalized knowledge is without value. On the contrary, such knowledge is essential for making predictions about the course of mental conditions and identifying effective treatments.
My point is that, if psychiatry is to be an epistemically just discipline, it must also find ways to engage with patients as epistemic agents. This would bring not only epistemic benefits but therapeutic ones as well. What is needed, in my view, is a collective theoretical effort comparable to the one that reoriented psychiatry toward standardization. We must now articulate the conditions under which attention to patients’ particularities and perspectives can also be regarded as objective.
Finally, if this analysis is correct, it has implications for the inclusion of patient perspectives in DSM revisions. While their inclusion will be bound to bring epistemic and therapeutic benefits, it falls short of addressing the complex realities of clinical practice.
Standardized instruments may vary in how well they achieve their theoretical and practical aims — and in the extent to which they promote epistemic and social practices that are just— but they will always be insufficient to fully address patients as unique subjects and as epistemic agents.