Wednesday, 18 June 2025

Digital Age: Mental Health, Cognitive Robotics, and AI

On the 9th of April 2025, Seiara Imanova organised an event, along with Andrew Hicklin, called "The Digital Age: Mental Health, Cognitive Robotics & AI", held at the Edgbaston campus, University of Birmingham as well as online. This post is a report of the event.


Speakers of The Digital Age event


The goal of the event was to highlight just how important the digital world has become, and the ways it’s shaping so many areas of our lives. As technology continues to shape how we communicate, understand who we are, and engage with systems of care, it’s crucial that we pause and critically examine what this means for fields like mental health, psychiatry, and beyond.


Seiara Imanova introduced Lucienne Spencer


The event began with an insightful presentation by Lucienne Spencer (University of Oxford), titled “Social Media & Shifts of Ontic Power in Mental Health”, which explored how digital spaces, such as social media platforms, can act as catalysts for shifts in psychiatric authority. In other words, online platforms like TikTok, Instagram as well as AI powered chatbots, are changing who gets to define, talk about, and influence mental health and psychiatry. Dr. Spencer highlights that although this shift could be considered a kind of ontic empowerment for people with mental ill health, re-shaping diagnostic categories in digital spaces carries the risk of distorting and diluting their original meaning.

Spencer’s presentation was followed by another incredible talk by Alan Winfield (University of Bristol), titled: “The Ethical Roboticist - From robot ethics to ethical robots”. Winfield looked at questions such as what do robot ethicists actually do, what kinds of harm can robots and AI cause, as well as ways for setting an ethical standard and regulations. Perhaps most striking was his demonstration of The AI Incidents Database, which highlighted why ethics was important in robotics, and how AI is already causing harm in the real world.


Alan Winfield's presentation


Last but most definitely not least, the third presentation was given by Paris Lalousis (King’s College London) titled: “Artificial Intelligence in Mental Health: Challenges, Pitfalls, and Opportunities” which is based on the excellent work he does at his AIM Lab at King’s. In contrast, Lalousis discussed the growing need for AI in healthcare, particularly in psychiatry, by highlighting the limitations of current neuroscientific approaches, such as the constraints of neuroimaging, the challenges posed by diagnostic ambiguity and high comorbidity rates between psychiatric conditions. 


Presentation by Paris Lalousis


Lalousis argued that intelligent systems hold significant potential to address these gaps. He presented his study on how the use of machine learning can better predict remission for patients with mental disorders such as schizophrenia or bipolar, and a glimpse into precision medicine.

The event hoped to achieve its goal which was to foster meaningful reflection on both the possibilities and ethical tensions that arise as human experience becomes more entangled with algorithmic and artificially intelligent systems. You can watch the live recording of the event below.




Wednesday, 11 June 2025

Metaphor and Epistemic Injustice in Schizophrenia

Today we interview Francesca Ervas and Lina Lissia on their project entitled: “Metaphor and Epistemic Injustice in Mental Illness: The Case of Schizophrenia” funded by PRIN, an Italian funding scheme to support research project of national interest. The project investigates epistemic injustice in metaphorical communication in the case of mental illness. A series of seminars has been planned as part of the project and the final meeting will be a conference held in Cagliari on 22-24 October 2025.


Metaphorical communication


Lisa: What are the research interests that gave rise to this project? 

Francesca and Lina: The project was born due to a common interest in metaphor as a way to express the self/mental illness relationship. The link with epistemic injustice, defined as the injustice towards a person as a knower, came later, and was based on the idea that metaphor can precisely be seen as an epistemic device. We were interested in both forms of epistemic injustice, as Miranda Fricker defined them in 2007: 1) as a failure to attribute credibility to people with mental illness (testimonial injustice), and 2) as an attempt to marginalize their epistemic resources thus not recognizing their ability to interpret their own experience of illness (hermeneutical injustice). 

The project builds on understanding and empirically investigating both the cognitive and social mechanisms behind testimonial and hermeneutical injustice, where people with mental illness often face epistemic challenges in credibility and interpretation. We hypothesized that metaphor can have a role as a communicative tool to overcome the ineffable and inarticulate nature of the mental illness experience and, notwithstanding social stigmas and interpretive difficulties, to reach an affective attunement with the relevant others (families, friends, doctors, healthcare professionals, other people in their social lives, etc.). 


Lisa: What are the main objectives of your project?

Francesca and Lina: Focusing on schizophrenia, the project analyzes the cognitive and bodily mechanisms at the root of the failure to attribute credibility (testimonial injustice) and interpretive capacities (hermeneutical injustice) to people with mental illness, when they communicate their illness to other people via metaphors vs. their literal counterparts.

We hypothesized that affective attunement in communication is a cooperative enterprise that needs to overcome both patients’ difficulties in embodying metaphors in illness communication and interpreters’ negative social and moral stereotypes, which concur to create the case for epistemic injustice.

The project involves three research units: the University of Cagliari (UniCa), the University of Messina (UniMe), and the University of Chieti (UniCh), respectively exploring:

  1. the interpreter’s perspective (UniCa, Prof. Francesca Ervas, PI of the project)
  2. the mental-ill speaker’s perspective (UniMe, Prof. Valentina Cuccio)
  3. the mental-ill speaker/interpreter interaction (UniCh, Prof. Francesca Ferri)

Such factors help us understand the cognitive mechanisms responsible for the missing attunement between people with mental illness and interpreters. 

Metaphor is proposed as a valuable resource to foster a better attunement between the speakers with schizophrenia and the interpreters and to possibly prevent or overcome epistemic injustice in illness communication. Metaphor is indeed a necessary tool for people with schizophrenia to express their illness and themselves in relationship with the illness, but also for relevant others to access what the speaker feels as meaningful to articulate of their experience of illness.


Working together


Lisa: Does your project involve different disciplines and perspectives? 

Francesca and Lina: The three research units have different disciplinary backgrounds and methodologies: philosophy of language and experimental pragmatics (UniCa); philosophy of mind and psycholinguistics (UniMe); cognitive neuroscience and psychiatry (UniCh). UniCa and UniMe embrace a theoretical-philosophical approach to the problem of epistemic injustice in the case of metaphor. 

All the units adopt an experimental approach to empirically investigate the cognitive mechanisms at the basis of the problem, focusing on schizophrenia. However, each unit tackles the very same problem from different angles and via different empirical methodologies. Check the members and the disciplinary background of all our teams.


Lisa: What do you expect the impact of this project to be?

Francesca and Lina: Results will significantly advance the understanding of the theoretical, linguistic and cognitive aspects of metaphor use in mental illness communication, with interdisciplinary scientific and academic impact and social impact on public policies and health institutions. A social campaign, based on the experimental data on metaphors production/understanding and the active engagement of stakeholders, will also be designed and produced, with an impact on the general public. 

Finally, the outcomes have the potential to lead to the development of novel rehabilitative interventions and novel social behaviors to prevent epistemic injustice.



The Metaphor and Epistemic Injustice in Schizophrenia project team:

Francesca Ervas, Martina Montalti, Valentina Cuccio, Alice Guerrieri, Francesca Ferri, Lucienne Huby, Lina Lissia.


Wednesday, 4 June 2025

Rethinking silence and epistemic agency in mental illness

In the scholarship on epistemic injustice and mental illness, silence figures almost exclusively as an epistemic harm. More specifically, we usually understand silence as a deficit in epistemic agency resulting from social prejudice or an unfair lack of adequate conceptual resources. Often that is indeed the case, and breaking such imposed and harmful silences is crucial for achieving epistemic justice.

However, this picture of silence is incomplete and potentially harmful. It ignores the possibility that silence can play an epistemically constructive role in the lives of people with mental illness, and that discouraging or breaking silence in such cases could be destructive. This is a possibility I explore in a recent article. Focusing on experiences of silence among people experiencing mania, I argue that silence can be a powerful act of epistemic agency – the capacity to acquire, maintain, and share knowledge competently and freely.


A woman peeks behind a corner, putting her finger to her lips as if to say 'shhh'


Epistemically agential silence

I articulate three kinds of epistemically agential silence: communicative silence, listening silence, and withholding silence. Each refers to a literal silence – an absence of speech or noise – through which a person is attempting to perform an epistemic action:

  1. Communicative silence is a silence through which a person intends to share knowledge with others. An example would be when you use your silence to express disapproval of something inappropriate someone has said.
  2. Listening silence is a silence through which a person intends to acquire knowledge from a speaker. An example would be when you fall silent in a conversation so your interlocutor can speak and you can hear what they have to say.
  3. Withholding silence is a silence through which a person intends to withhold knowledge from others. The function of such a silence might be to maintain knowledge, as when you decide not to share something with a person who might manipulate you into thinking you are mistaken. Its function can also be to avoid sharing knowledge, as you might do when you know an audience isn’t equipped to understand what you have to say.

These silences are plausibly important for everyone, but they seem particularly important for those who experience mania.


Two men sit in chairs both both are silent. One leans forward in anticipation, the other leans back as if they don't want to contribute to the conversation.


Losing silence in mania

Two common symptoms of mania are increased talkativeness and an uncontrollable urge to speak. First-person accounts suggest that people with these symptoms often find that their capacity to perform epistemically agential silence has been impaired.

Some describe losing the ability to perform listening silence. For example, in her memoir of living with bipolar disorder, Terri Cheney describes how, when she was severely manic, she’d become unable to ‘shut up and listen’. Another writer with bipolar, Bassey Ikpi, says that in mania she sometimes 'couldn’t remember how to quiet her brain enough to listen’.

Others report becoming unable to perform withholding silence. For instance, one contributor to a bipolar forum says that when she is manic, she does not ‘know how to stop talking’ and ends up telling everyone that she has bipolar, even if they have no need to know or are prejudiced or ignorant about mental illness.

This can have a profoundly negative impact on individuals with mania. Losing the capacity for silence can deprive them of vital information and undermine their support networks. Meanwhile, losing the capacity for withholding silence may lead individuals to reveal information about themselves and their illness in circumstances where disclosure might expose them to misunderstanding or discrimination.

People who experience mania are often well aware of these risks. Therefore, when they feel their capacity for silence is deteriorating, they may look for new ways to stay silent when they need to—for example, by clenching their jaw, jiggling their leg, or digging their nails into their palms. For them, silence is not an epistemic harm but a hard-won epistemic achievement.


A person leans back in a chair in quiet satisfaction.


The costs of misunderstanding silence

So silence can clearly have significant epistemic value for people with mania. This is why the assumption that silence is a sign of epistemic injustice may inadvertently perpetuate or even exacerbate harm. For example, it may prompt a well-intentioned individual to misunderstand a manic person’s epistemically agential silence as evidence of epistemic oppression and, therefore, seek to break their silence, perhaps by urging them to speak. That may end up undermining the epistemic agency of the manic person and expose them to epistemic and hazards they were trying avoid through silence.

To avoid contributing to this, those of us researching epistemic injustice must begin to explicitly acknowledge in our work that silence is a diverse phenomenon. Sometimes it does represent epistemic oppression. But it can also be empowering, constituting a vital epistemic tactic that ill persons and other vulnerable individuals use to navigate complex interpersonal, institutional, and social landscapes. If analyses of epistemic injustice in healthcare and beyond are to be relevant and helpful, this is not something we can ignore.


Portrait of Dan Degerman

Dan Degerman is a Research Fellow on the EPIC project and a AHRC Research, Development, and Engagement Fellow on the 'Beyond Voice' project. His current research explores the relationship between silence and epistemic injustice in bipolar disorder.