Wednesday, 20 November 2024

Hysteria, Hermeneutical Injustice and Conceptual Engineering

In "Hysteria, Hermeneutical Injustice, and Conceptual Engineering", I look at what Miranda Fricker, in her Epistemic Injustice. Power and the Ethics of Knowing (2007) calls “hermeneutical injustice”, as it arises in the medical context. By drawing on the complex history of hysteria, I argue that the very concept HYSTERIA was used for diagnostic purposes for millennia, before its dismissal with the DSM-III in 1980, due to power structures affected by negative prejudice against women. 


Stereotypical representation of hysteria


I then argue that HYSTERIA fits the central conditions of the concept HERMENEUTICAL INJUSTICE. Yet, reflection on the case of HYSTERIA also signals the need for widening the understanding of the concept HERMENEUTICAL INJUSTICE itself. This is methodologically important for two reasons. First, because instead of considering the medical field merely as an area of application or testing of philosophical ideas, it uses medical data to improve a philosophical notion. Accordingly, I propose that hermeneutical injustice may depend not only on gaps in hermeneutical resources, but also on the presence of faulty ones, such as HYSTERIA. 

Second, once thus improved upon, HERMENEUTICAL INJUSTICE can be used to advocate for other forms of amelioration of concepts, which still embed identity prejudice against certain groups. I claim that it can do so by eschewing the more traditional path taken in current debates on the amelioration of concepts such as WOMAN. These debates risk perpetrating an “essentialist” outlook – let it be grounded in biological “nature” or in socially-acquired “nature” – on what women “really” are (or should be), which is fraught with problems.

By bringing the concept of HERMENEUTICAL INJUSTICE to bear onto this kind of discussion we can bypass that “essentialist” outlook altogether and be more inclusive and open to further applications of WOMAN, if these applications can help people, such as transwomen, to make sense of their experience and if doing so can help remove identity prejudice against them. 

The debate over the concept WOMAN is but one example of the areas in which a reconfigured concept of HERMENEUTICAL INJUSTICE could play a role. In fact, once so reconfigured, HERMENEUTICAL INJUSTICE could also be used to diagnose what is epistemically amiss in the use of those slurs, epithets and pejoratives which likewise embed identity prejudice against certain groups.

In fact, HYSTERIA is a clear example of a harmful concept rooted in identity prejudice against women. Its use undermines women’s ability to understand, express, and reason about their experiences, perpetuating forms of epistemic injustice like testimonial and what I call “rational(ity) injustice”— that is, the injustice of downplaying, diminishing and impeding the development of women’s rational abilities, due to identity prejudice against them. Therefore, I argue that using “hysterical"” and related terms descriptively should be banned.

Still, HYSTERIA could potentially be reclaimed by women, like other harmful concepts rooted in identity prejudice that were initially rejected for their damaging effects but later embraced by marginalized groups to strenghten identity and belonging.



Annalisa Coliva is Professor of Philosophy at University of California Irvine, and Editor in Chief of the Journal for the History of Analytic Philosophy

Annalisa's interests are in Epistemology, Philosophy of mind and language, and History of Analytic Philosophy.

Wednesday, 13 November 2024

Stigma as a Barrier to Self-Understanding

This blogpost is written by Alexander Edlich and Alfred Archer, writing about their recent paper in Social Epistemology entitled 'Rejecting Identities: Stigma and Hermeneutical Injustice'.

To seek, and accept, medical help, it is often necessary to realize that one needs it. Sometimes, however, people refuse to accept they need help, and this disables them from accessing medical resources. This refusal need not be due to stubbornness but can be the result of unjust social factors. In particular, we suggest that stigma can unjustly prevent people from making sense of their situation, including stigmatized illnesses. 

Take, for instance, the American writer Caroline Knapp’s account of her struggle to accept the idea that she was an alcoholic in her memoir Drinking: A Love Story. She describes how at times she was so drunk that she would ‘drive home with one eye shut, to avoid double vision’ (p. 54). 

After being advised by her therapist that she should stop drinking, she decided to attend an Alcoholics Anonymous meeting. Once in the meeting though, she felt a strong revulsion to accepting that she belonged there. As she describes it, she “looked around at the dingy room with the old men sipping coffee from foam cups and I thought, No way. No way in hell I’m doing this. This is not me. I do not belong here’ (pp. 190–191).

For Knapp to accept that she was an alcoholic would mean ‘owning up to flaws and imperfections and depths of confusion I was too ashamed to reveal’. This shame that she felt about her alcoholism was a response to the social stigma attached to it. Even when she had accepted her alcoholism and stopped drinking, Knapp continued to be very careful about which people she would discuss it with ‘for fear of being judged’ (p. 244). 

What prevented Knapp first from accepting and even longer from communicating about her situation was the stigma attached to alcoholism, and thus a social factor burdening those suffering from it. This made it harder for her to seek help.


The cover of Knapp's book


Knapp is far from alone in struggling with this, the stigma attached to alcoholism is a significant barrier to people seeking out medical assistance. This difficulty in accepting one’s addiction is a major problem, given that this acceptance is crucial for overcoming the addiction and also for seeking help in the first place.

While medical professionals are aware of the importance of reducing the stigma attached to medical conditions like addiction, the impact of stigma on self-understanding is not only practical, but, we argue, also creates a particular type of hermeneutical injustice: those whose experiences are stigmatized are unjustly made to reject helpful descriptions of their situation.

Hermeneutical injustice is the label philosophers use, coined by Miranda Fricker, to describe cases where the social practices of knowing, learning, and communicating are unjust so that persons in particular social positions are deprived of the means to make sense of their experiences. In paradigmatic cases, this occurs because dominant discourses do not include concepts that are needed to make sense of the experiences of marginally situated agents.  

For example, Fricker argues that before the development of the concept ‘sexual harassment’ people who experienced unwanted sexual attention in the workplace were not able to properly name their experiences. In this case, they were unfairly prevented from fully understanding the situation they were in because they lacked the concepts needed to articulate what it is they were experiencing, which, consequently, also disabled them from sharing their experiences. 

The stigma related to addiction (and other stigmatized experiences, like homosexuality or suffering intimate partner violence) also unfairly prevents people from making sense of their experiences but does so in a subtly different way. Here the conceptual resources are available to people. The concept of an alcoholic or an addict was available to Knapp and once she accepted that it applied to her, she was able to access the resources she needed to manage her addiction, including a supportive community of people struggling with the same problem. 

What prevented Knapp from accessing these resources was not the absence of a concept but the stigma that was attached to it. Knapp denied herself access to the hermeneutic resources that go with the label ‘alcoholic’ because of the stigma attached to this identity, which led her to refuse to accept that the label applied to her. In this way, stigma can unjustly cause people to reject helpful descriptions of their situation or identity.

To come to terms with a condition like addiction and to seek help about it, it is important to understand one’s situation and to accept it. Some people refuse such acceptance, and they can suffer gravely from it. This is a problem for medical practice, but, importantly, it can also be a problem of justice: to offer help, but also to treat people justly, we must make sure that stigma does not stand in the way of self-understanding.


Alexander Edlich completed his PhD at Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität Munich in 2023, where he then was a postdoctoral researcher. He works on moral responsibility (specifically blame, protest, and apology), the philosophy of emotions, and feminist and LGBTQ ethics.

Alfred Archer is Associate Professor of Philosophy at Tilburg University. He is interested in ethics, social philosophy, philosophy of sport, and moral psychology. He is the co-author of Honouring and Admiring the Immoral: An Ethical Guide (Routledge 2021), Why It’s OK to be a Sports Fan (Routledge 2024) and Extravagance and Misery: The Emotional Regime of Market Societies (OUP 2024).

Wednesday, 6 November 2024

Epistemic Isolation in Psychiatric Healthcare

This blog is based on an article by Dr Lucienne Spencer which was published last month in the journal Social Epistemology.

Kidd and Carel’s concept of ‘epistemic isolation’ occurs in ‘situations where a person or group lacks the knowledge of, or means of access to, particular information’ (Kidd and Carel 2017, 183–184). Such epistemic isolation can be found in psychiatric healthcare, where treatment plans and even diagnoses can be withheld from the patient (Spencer, 2024).

Goldstein distinguishes between epistemic isolation as an epistemic injustice or as an epistemic disadvantage (Goldstein 2022). Not all epistemic harms are necessarily epistemic injustices, but rather ‘circumstantial epistemic bad luck’ (Fricker 2007, 152). While Fricker limits ‘epistemic bad luck’ to the product of ‘hermeneutical disadvantage’, Goldstein broadens this notion to ‘Epistemic Disadvantage’, which occurs when a person or group is excluded from knowledge in a warranted way, even if it results in intellectual or moral harm.

A thinking head


Goldstein argues epistemic isolation is an epistemic disadvantage when it meets the following criteria:

  1. ‘Harms are non-deliberate, arising in circumstances of bad luck’.
  2. ‘Speakers lack precision or mastery of concepts to effectively communicate their experience’.
  3. ‘Affected participants are justifiably excluded or subordinated from the practice that could make the concept known’. (Goldstein 2022, 1870–1871)

Here, I examine Goldstein’s criteria in relation to epistemic isolation in psychiatric healthcare.  

Criteria 1

For Fricker, epistemic injustice is necessarily non-deliberative. The epistemic injustices she conceives of are ‘discriminatory but ingenuous misjudgement’ rather than ‘deliberate manipulation’ (Fricker 2017, 54). Therefore, unintentional epistemic harm is not unique to epistemic disadvantage.

As Goldstein observes, epistemic injustice must be motivated by an identity prejudice. To refer to epistemic isolation in psychiatric healthcare as an instance of ‘bad luck’ would be to assume that it is merely circumstantial that the clinician does not have time to meet the patient’s epistemic needs: to ensure they understand their treatment and diagnosis. However, this so-called ‘bad luck’ is driven by what Fricker calls an ‘institutional epistemic vice’ in the healthcare system (Fricker 2021).

Institutional epistemic vice is a culpable lapse in the institution’s epistemic ethos (Fricker 2021, 101). Fricker imagines a school with good epistemic commitments but has developed ‘sloppy information sharing’ (Fricker 2021, 100). Similarly, the psychiatric healthcare system has a good ethos, yet flawed information-sharing practices and an institutional attitude that deprioritises the epistemic needs of the patient. This epistemic isolation emerges from a structural identity prejudice that is not located in the clinician but, rather, in the bones of the institution.

Criteria 2

Here, we need to determine if an inability to effectively communicate emerges from a ‘lack of mastery’ or from hermeneutical injustice. A ‘lack of precision or mastery of concepts’ may simply be a lack of mastery in the imposed interpretive framework. One may have a good capacity for communicating one’s experience in one’s own words, beyond a clinical framework; however, such communication is not understood or taken seriously.

Instead, we can ask whether there is a just division in epistemic labour between experts and non-experts. Goldstein follows Goldman in defining an expert as those with a ‘superior quantity or level of knowledge in some domain and an ability to generate new knowledge in that domain’ (Goldman 2001, 91). Clinicians, indeed, have developed skills in their field and act as generators of knowledge. However, those with psychiatric illness hold a unique form of experiential knowledge and expertise.

Illness ‘gives us experiences that we would not otherwise have had and that we cannot know what it is like to have until we undergo them’ (Carel et al. 2016, 1152). Therefore, if we take the ‘domain’ to be the psychiatric illness under evaluation, psychiatric patients cannot be said to lack a ‘superior quantity or level of knowledge’ or ‘an ability to generate new knowledge’. If the patient is treated as a non-expert from the outset, and knowledge is withheld, they are deprived of the opportunity to ‘master the concepts to effectively communicate their experience’. Instead, ignorance is imposed upon the patient from the offset.

Criteria 3

Clinical institutions could attempt to justify withholding information through the ‘non-maleficence principle’, the idea that revealing a diagnosis or treatment plan will cause harm to the patient. Alternatively, it could be argued that the deprioritisation of the patient’s epistemic needs is justified due to limits on time and resources. However, withholding information from a patient often causes the patient more harm than good (Spencer, 2024).

Most significantly, institutionalised epistemic isolation places the patient at a ‘cognitive disadvantage’. As such, they are inhibited not only from contributing to the pool of knowledge regarding their illness but also from making sense of their illness themselves. Although the diagnosis may be withheld due to the fear of stigmatisation, it is the stigmatisation that causes harm, not the diagnosis itself. This stigmatisation is only exacerbated by a culture of silence around the diagnosis.

Goldstein provides a valuable development of epistemic isolation, and I share her concern for overstretching the term epistemic injustice beyond the unjust. I show that epistemic isolation in psychiatric healthcare is not such a case of epistemic disadvantage.


Lucienne Spencer
Lucienne is a a Postdoctoral Researcher in Mental Health Ethics located within the Neuroscience, Ethics and Society (NEUROSEC) Team in the Department of Psychiatry, University of Oxford. Her research primarily focuses on phenomenology, epistemic injustice and the philosophy of psychiatry. 

Wednesday, 30 October 2024

Narrative Deference

This blog post is a write-up of a paper by project postdoc Ellie Byrne which was published in Topoi in September as part of a special issue entitled Scaffolding Bad: Varieties of Situated Cognitive Harm edited by David Spurrett, Giovanna Colombetti and John Sutton. 

When I worked on the project Grief: A Study of Human Emotional Experience (PI Matthew Ratcliffe) at York, we obtained hundreds of first-person testimonies from grieving people about their experiences. I think regularly about some of the things people wrote, but there’s one in particular I keep coming back to: “My childhood is now only remembered by me. I’m an only child. So that time seems completely inaccessible.” (#208)

To me, this quote drew attention to the extent to which having other people available to corroborate our memories influences how we understand ourselves. We do this all the time and all throughout our lives: we might ask our parents to corroborate some significant childhood experience of ours, or ask a sibling to confirm that we’ve remembered something correctly. Later in life, we may ask a friend to corroborate how we remember coping with a breakup or our partner to remind us of a certain order of events in a particularly busy period.

We also enlist others to fill in the gaps for things we do not remember well. We might not really remember much at all about these experiences; perhaps just diffuse ‘feelings’ associated with certain events. In such cases, we might end up pretty reliant on our friends, family and partners to tell us what happened, how we felt about what happened and how those feelings have shaped who we are today.

According to the philosopher Richard Heersmink, autobiographical memories are the building blocks of our autobiographical self-narratives. Heersmink, situating some of his work within the field of ‘distributed cognition’, has emphasised that since our memories are distributed between people, it makes sense to say that our self-narratives are too. In my paper, I followed Heersmink in drawing attention to the extent to which we can rely on others for our autobiographical self-narratives, and the ways that this can be both good and bad for us. My paper introduces a concept which I call ‘narrative deference’, defined as the phenomenon whereby one is more dependent upon another person for central aspects of one’s autobiographical self-narrative than on oneself.

As I started to present this idea at conferences and workshops, there was a consistent theme in Q&A discussions: each time, multiple people in the audience had thought of contexts in which this phenomenon is harmful. This led me to think about the phenomenon in terms of another one of my research interests: affective injustice.

Affective injustice scholar Shiloh Whitney connects affective injustice to a distinctively affective form of gaslighting, the phenomena whereby casting doubt on someone is the means through which they are made to doubt themselves: “in gaslighting, the way others respond to me begins to impair an aspect of my relationship to myself. In particular, the noncooperative response I receive from some second person(s) when I express my experiences to them begins to impair some aspect of my ability to make sense of my own experience to myself in the first person” (Whitney 2023, pp.31–32). 

Understood this way, we can see how the affective influence others have on us can be used to undermine our self-trust over time such that our autobiographical self-narrative possibilities are restricted. While gaslighting is primarily discussed in the context of romantic relationships, it is being increasingly recognised how gaslighting can also occur in healthcare settings.

In a variety of contexts, an ill person might narratively defer to another because it presents itself as the best immediate option. Perhaps narratively deferring to my parents allows me to maintain a coherent or desirable autobiographical self-narrative. Perhaps deferring to my doctor allows me to make sense of an otherwise overwhelming and confusing situation. Perhaps deferring to my partner prevents conflict and maintains my bond with the person who cares for me. This deference can surely help me to secure lots of things that are good for me, but my most fundamental sense of self is also made vulnerable by it.

I think there is a lot of interesting and important future work to be done in exploring how this phenomenon operates in both epistemic and affective injustices in healthcare.


Eleanor Byrne
Eleanor is a postdoctoral research fellow at the University of Birmingham and part of Project EPIC. She specialises in affective and existential dimensions of illness experiences, particularly Functional Neurological Disorders. She has worked on grief in illness and experiences of post-viral fatigue such as Long Covid. She is currently developing a project on phenomenology and functional seizures. 




Wednesday, 23 October 2024

Communicating Ineffable Experiences

On the occasion of the Research & Development (R&D) Conference 2024 on October 15th, Jodie Russell, postdoctoral researcher on project EPIC, presented her work on ineffable experiences and the phenomenology of language to the Herefordshire and Worcestershire Health and Care NHS Trust.

In this post, Jodie summarises the key points in her talk.

Two people struggle to understand one another
Ineffability


Language as gesture

I want to make the case that it is possible for people who don’t themselves experience mental disorder to understand the experiences of those who do, even when these individuals struggle to communicate their experiences. This recognition is important as it may help us overcome some epistemic injustices as a result of assuming some experiences are un-understandable and therefore not worth trying to understand.

To make my case, I argue that we should take a phenomenological approach to language, drawing on French philosopher Maurice Merleau-Ponty for this purpose. On the phenomenological view, language is much more than the words on the page or the sounds that come out of our mouths; for Merleau-Ponty, language is a gesture at the world, which our whole body is involved in. When we speak, we are 'geared' towards the world in a particular way.

For example, when I talk about my cat Fluffy sitting on the mat, I’m gesturing toward Fluffy with my words, in the same way that I might point at Fluffy with my finger. My statement also indicates Fluffy’s ‘presence’; my statement turns us towards Fluffy in our shared world. At my mention, you might look for her or anticipate her to appear, for example, even if she’s actually just hopped out the cat flap.

A cat winking
A cat



The horizon of ideas

My language also implies certain things about me, the world I live in and the nature of Fluffy. For example, I live in a world where cats are domesticated. Her name also tells you that she’s a cat with a significant coat (hence her name) who is well known to me. Language, in the way that it points to aspects of the world, also implies further ideas beyond what we merely see; this is what Hayden Kee (2020) refers to as the ‘horizon’ of ideas.

Importantly, we are aware of other ideas implied by our language in virtue of being part of a shared world. As members of a linguistic community, we all contribute to a stock of shared meanings by both introducing new meanings, changing the old meanings, or reinforcing the old meanings. Which kinds of contribution we make depends on the context (my old saying maybe new to your ears, and thus I may contribute something new – in one way - to our personal pool of shared meanings). Nevertheless, we are, I claim, inherently embedded in a linguistic community and thus our language is (almost) inescapable from this pool of shared meanings.

A figure looks out at the horizon
Horizon


Sharing a linguistic community 

Individuals with ineffable disorder experiences are part of the linguistic community too; they may lack words for their experiences because there simply is no way to describe them in our community. But that doesn’t make their experiences totally incommunicable, I argue. We may just have to understand communication as being broader than words (someone may indicate with their body how they feel, and it is up to us to take up this meaning and try to integrate in into our horizon of ideas).

We must also acknowledge that describing an experience as ineffable is still, itself, communicating some of the experience. We may then need to tease apart the implications of that for other areas of the individual’s life (how they feel they live with an experience that can’t describe, e.g., as a mother, a friend or a working professional) to work around the areas that are more difficult to express.

Understanding individuals with mental disorder to be a part of our linguistic community, of which we are all inherently embedded, is key, I think, to overcoming some of the communicative issues that can arise when someone lacks words for a complex experience, and to gaining valuable insight into what it is like for them to live with said experiences.

Wednesday, 16 October 2024

Epistemic injustice and diagnostic approaches to mental ill-health

Epistemic injustice is evident in a plethora of contexts, some institutional, for which the discourse of hermeneutical injustice offers a helpful frame by way of its negotiation of meaning. Examples could include different treatments administered by healthcare institutions that unfortunately limit a patient’s voice and visibility. Other instances are well-trodden in the literature and media, and remain ever present, including gender and race issues, as presented by wide-ranging movements like Black Lives Matter and #MeToo.

A megaphone

Some examples of epistemic injustice are close to home and, sometimes, in the home. Relationships that once thrived can fracture when under sufficient pressure, whether between intimates, blood relations or in-laws, or something more general like the bonds between friends and other associates. In the throes of such breaks, testimonial injustice might be at work, concerned as this is with semiotic ruptures in spoken utterances that displace kindly intentions and good will. 

Where relational intimacy intersects with discourses that organise bonding experiences, for example, some kinds of religion and politics, the distinctions between hermeneutical and testimonial injustices are difficult to identify. The cliché that what is today’s deviance becomes tomorrow’s norm is continually challenged by the vicissitudes of lived experience that make possible the very identification of deviancy and normativity. The making of necessary interventions is, in this regard, highly problematic and, when it occurs in its zenith form, an achievement.

In 2021 my Master by Research dissertation, which explored some of these questions, was accepted in the University of Wales Trinity Saint David. My thesis, titled Diagnosis, misdiagnosis, and becoming better: An investigation into epistemic injustice and mental health, focused on diagnostic issues in the treatment of mental ill-health. Its main focus was to contextualise observations sometimes termed “empirical” by considering some of the existential contexts that experients of mental health treatment might find themselves in.

It is naturally the case that in an acute state, the solutions common to the biomedical model of mental ill-health are readily reached for. If a person suffers a psychotic breakdown then administering an antipsychotic drug could be a profoundly helpful and practical way of relieving distress. But there are many social domains that circumscribe, penetrate and, in turn, shape an individual’s diverse experiences of society. As well as religion, family, politics and the State, they could also include the stories we tell that frame those very societal categories. Psychoanalysis, literature, film and sociology are a handful of subject-disciplines that present telling-truth and telling-detail by offering “ways forward and out” of profoundly difficult moments in the life-course. My belief is that any line of enquiry that enables an experient to learn constructively and “re-find their feet”, so-to-speak, is both directive and instructive.


Antipsychotic medication

Concerned as it is with the mind as an aspect of embodiment that is organising as much as organised my research explores modes of being-and-becoming. In this regard, I am interested in two broad areas of exploration: first the clinical tools that enable a growth mind-set, whether employed by experients or physicians. Second, I lay out some of the general principles that might categorise those tools as philosophically resonant. They could be of a testimonial variety by highlighting signs and symbolic structures generative of psychosocial capacitation. 

Other, hermeneutical kinds may point to the diverse social movements that can lead an experient out of different forms of fog and miasma commonplace in contested diagnoses and misdiagnoses. In showing the presence and gravity of an epistemic injustice, there is laid the groundwork for a theoretical space where the experient can incrementally attain functionality. They may find ways of learning that which they themselves need vitally such that self-understanding becomes a real possibility. They might even encounter levels of personal, interpersonal and social responsivity expressive of epistemic justice and accountability.

Martyn Sampson

Martyn Sampson is an independent researcher of the philosophy of psychiatry and mental health. He is presently working on an extended project on stigma and phenomenology in regard to different psychiatric conditions.

Thursday, 10 October 2024

Project EPIC on World Mental Health Day 2024





On the occasion of World Mental Health Day (#WMHD2024), we asked project EPIC team members to share a quote and a resource relevant to their work on epistemic injustice in healthcare.


Jodie Russell




Jodie is a researcher working at the University of Birmingham on one of EPIC case studies. Jodie is the author of "Problems for Enactive Psychiatry as a Practical Framework", published open access in Philosophical Psychology, highlighting the limitations of enactivism in reducing the harm and suffering experienced by individuals diagnosed with mental disorders.

 

Lisa Bortolotti




Lisa is an investigator in project EPIC, based at the University of Birmingham. Lisa has co-authored with Kathleen Murphy-Hollies a paper entitled "Why We Should Be Curious about Each Other", published open access in Philosophies, arguing that curiosity a good antidote to epistemic injustice. Lisa also edited and contributed a chapter to the forthcoming open access book on Epistemic Justice in Mental Healthcare (Palgrave Pivot).


Dan Degerman




Dan is a researcher on project EPIC, based at the University of Bristol. Dan's research explores the idea that it might not always be good to talk about one's mental health. If you want to know more, you can read Dan's article written for the Conversation.


Havi Carel




Havi is project EPIC principal investigator, based at the University of Bristol. Havi's work focuses on the experience of illness and she pioneered the application of the notion of epistemic injustice to healthcare. Watch this video where she introduces project EPIC.


Rabih Chattat




Rabih is a project EPIC partner, based at the University of Bologna. Rabih's work focuses on psychosocial interventions in dementia and the clinical psychology of ageing. He recently wrote a post for the EPIC blog on good living and social health as applied to dementia. Rabih also contributed a chapter on these themes to the forthcoming open access book on Epistemic Justice in Mental Healthcare (Palgrave Pivot).


Jude Williams



Jude is the project manager for EPIC at the University of Birmingham. Jodie volunteers for the Choir with No Name, the choir that gives homeless people a voice. If you want to know more about what the Choir is about and what impact it has, please read this.


Matthew Broome





Matthew is an investigator on EPIC and directs the Institute of Mental Health at the University of Birmingham. He recently co-authored a paper with Lucienne Spencer on epistemic injustice and claims of suicidality that can be found here. Together with Michael Larkin, Lisa Bortolotti, and Rose McCabe, Matthew contributed a chapter on youth mental health to the forthcoming open access book on Epistemic Justice in Mental Healthcare (Palgrave Pivot).


Eleanor Byrne




Eleanor is a researcher on project EPIC, based at the University of Birmingham. Eleanor works in the philosophy of medicine, on conditions that impact on the mental and physical capacities of those affected. In this podcast, she discusses an area at the intersection of philosophy and psychotherapy, focusing on experiences of fatigue.


Elisabetta Lalumera




Elisabetta is an EPIC project partner based at the University of Bologna. Elisabetta works in the philosophy of medicine. You can read this blog post where she talks about how to achieve epistemic justice in the biomedical paradigm. Elisabetta also contributed a chapter on digital health technologies to the forthcoming open access book on Epistemic Justice in Mental Healthcare (Palgrave Pivot).


Rose McCabe




Rose is an EPIC project partner based at City University, London. Rose specialises in research on clinical communication and contributes to the design of interventions to improve the capacity of professionals to listen to people who seek support for their mental health. See an example here. Together with Michael Larkin, Lisa Bortolotti, and Matthew Broome, Rose contributed a chapter on youth mental health to the forthcoming open access book on Epistemic Justice in Mental Healthcare (Palgrave Pivot).


Lara Calabrese



Lara is interested in ways of explaining and ameliorating the stigmatisation of people with dementia. She is a researcher at the University of Bologna, and is going to collect the data for one of EPIC case studies. 


Luigi Grassi




Luigi is an EPIC project partner, working at the University of Ferrara. Luigi recently shared some of this research interests in dignity and stigma in end of life care on the EPIC blog. Luigi also contributed a chapter on these themes to the forthcoming open access book on Epistemic Justice in Mental Healthcare (Palgrave Pivot)


Kathleen Murphy-Hollies




Kathleen is a researcher at the University of Birmingham. Kathleen has worked with some entomologists to better understand delusions of parasitosis, when people come to believe that their bodies have been infested by insects. To know more about this fascinating condition and the challenges it poses, go here.


Martino Belvederi Murri




Martino is an EPIC project partner, working at the University of Ferrara. Martino recently shared of his research interests in demoralisation and testimonial injustice in an acute psychiatric ward on the EPIC blog. Martino also contributed a chapter on these themes to the forthcoming open access book on Epistemic Justice in Mental Healthcare (Palgrave Pivot).

Wednesday, 2 October 2024

Understanding Oneself through Others Day 2

This is a report by Jodie Russell and Lisa Bortolotti. On 23rd and 24th September Eleanor Byrne and Kathleen Murphy-Hollies organised a workshop at the University of Birmingham, bringing together researchers interested in the area of the intersection of epistemic injustice and distributed cognition. The venue for the workshop was the beautiful Winterbourne House and Garden. 

You find a report of day one here.


Winterbourne


On day two, Katherine Puddifoot offered her keynote presentation, entitled "Affect, Attention, and Injustice: The Injustice of Neglected Affect". Katherine started from the observation that affective states, like anxiety, worsen in some illnesses like COPD (Chronic obstructive pulmonary disease). Should we draw attention to those affective states? The talk focused on there being an injustice of Neglected Affect. The injustice occurs where people have affective states like fear and anxiety which are preventing them from having their objective basic needs like health, education, and longevity met.


Slide from Katherine Puddifoot's presentation


The people who are experiencing the affect could benefit from being given information about their affective states and how to modulate them. However, drawing attention to the affect risks leading them to engage in negative self-stereotyping, and fear judgement and generally distrust others—each of which could prevent them from gaining knowledge and understanding about their affective states and how to modulate them. 

This presents an epistemic dilemma for those who notice that others have affective states like fear and anxiety that are undermining their objective basic needs: whether they draw attention to the affective states or not, they risk causing the person experiencing the affect to miss out on knowledge and understanding about how to modulate it. Already vulnerable people, who possess affective states that are negatively impacting their objective basic needs, are further disadvantaged because they are unable to access knowledge and understanding that would support their objective basic needs by modulating their affect. 


J.P. Grodniewicz is presenting and Ellie Byrne chairing

The second talk was by J.P. Grodniewicz and Anna Drożdżowicz, and concerned epistemic injustice in the context of psychotherapy. For J.P, and Anna, psychotherapy is a form of psychological service that involves a collaborative process based on the relationship between (at least one) psychotherapist and (at least one) client/patient. Although psychotherapy can be a valuable experience with multiple positive outcomes, the path to achieving these outcomes may be long and difficult. Specifically, in some cases, patients/clients can be vulnerable to various forms of harm and injustice.

In this talk, they discussed the epistemic goals of psychotherapy and specific risks related to clients’/patients’ attempts to achieve these goals. First, they argued that the main epistemic goal of psychotherapy is deepening one’s self-understanding, characterized as a kind of objectual understanding which consists of grasping coherence-making relations between constituents of a body of information about oneself.

Second, they argued that patients/clients may risk various forms of epistemic injustice that may further hinder them from acquiring and/or deepening self-understanding in psychotherapy. Epistemic injustice arises when one’s capacity as an epistemic agent is denied. Epistemic injustice is widely discussed in the context of psychiatry; however, epistemic injustice in psychotherapy has received relatively little attention.

They offered examples that illustrate how three forms of epistemic injustice can arise in psychotherapeutic encounters:

  • Testimonial injustice in psychotherapy occurs when the client’s words and/or capacity to provide knowledge are wrongfully assigned less credibility by the psychotherapist due to epistemically irrelevant factors rooted in systematic or interpersonal dynamics.
  • Hermeneutical injustice in psychotherapy occurs when clients are wronged in their capacity to make sense of their experiences due to limitations in their conceptual resources or due to having the conceptual resources of the psychotherapist imposed on them against their interest(s).
  • Contributory injustice occurs in psychotherapy when clients cannot contribute their perspectives and interpretations because their contribution is dismissed or undermined by the psychotherapist.

In each case, they argued that epistemic injustice may result in specific epistemic harms related to achieving and/or deepening one’s self-understanding in the course of psychotherapy. In the end, they briefly discussed some ways of mitigating these risks.


Slide from David Hahn's presentation


The third talk was by David Hahn and was entitled: "Self-Illness Ambiguity, Alienation, and Distributed Self-Understanding". David started from the observation that feeling uncertain about who we are can affect our agency and our relationships so it is important to resolve self-illness ambiguity. But how should we do so? In realist accounts, what is internal is who we really are but mental illness is simplified as it appears like a virus that "attacks" the self. The self is actually more intertwined and complex; the definition of what 'self' is, is a judgement or decision.

Self-discovery approaches presuppose self-knowledge, and reify both the self and illness. Most authors advocate for a narrative view of the self that can be just as reifying as the realist view even if the self is constructed. One of course could ask whether the narrative is "good" in the sense of authentic, but this may not be helpful to someone who is experiencing self-illness ambiguity.

If we reject both realist and constructivist view of the self-illness ambiguity, what is left? The self is not constituted of new facts but interpretations and a critical theory is needed, drawn from Jaeggi's account of alienation. On Jaeggi's account, alienation is a relation of relationlessness, a disrupted appropriation of inner and outer world. It is not to be understood as a lack of knowledge but as an inability to lead one's life, due to an alienated relationship between self and world.

So, overcoming ambiguities doesn't involve asking what is "really me" but, instead, asking practical-ethical questions in the process of learning how to live an unalienated life.


Slide from the presentation by Vespermann and Tirkkonen


Daniel Vespermann and Sanna Tirkkonen discussed existential injustice and focused on the phenomena of background feelings (which are phenomenologically different from emotions). Distressing background feelings of uncertainty, existential guilt, or worthlessness are enduring and remain unaffected by momentary changes of social situations. These feelings condition episodic emotions, thought processes, and behavioral tendencies. As affective states, they also impact on a person’s commitments, concerns, and values. Background feelings thus have an important guiding function in our lives.

Daniel and Sanna argued that distressing feelings require hermeneutic labor and prompt regulatory efforts, which are often scaffolded by the social environment. Given this premise, background feelings are generally vulnerable to unjust social influences. Despite the burgeoning literature on affective injustice and hostile scaffolding, how background feelings can be subject to social injustice has remained underdeveloped in these debates.

Because of their fundamental role for people’s affective, cognitive, and practical capacities, Daniel and Sanna call the wronging of background feelings existential injustice. They introduced two dimensions of existential injustice that lead to feelings of inadequacy and thus exacerbate mental distress. First, attention guidance and narrative practices can impede understanding and regulating one’s background feelings by limiting potential perspectives on one’s affective condition.

Second, they analyzed the regulatory role of attention guidance. Patterns of attention predetermine sources of affect regulation. Directing attention away from distressing stimuli or thoughts again helps to modulate emotional strain. However, what becomes perceptually salient is shaped in specific sociocultural contexts and these selection histories can lead to maladaptive adaptations to context-specific values.

Third, Daniel and Sanna clarified the idea that different narrative practices shape self-relevant information. Since narratives can be a means of determining criteria for the appropriateness and fittingness of affective states, they may also impose unjust demands on individuals’ affect regulation. Thus, narrative practices can generate cognitive frames that prevent beneficial reappraisals of affective interaction patterns.

Together, these dimensions reinforce the painful salience of distressing background feelings and foreclose experiences of support or validation. Being hindered from reframing one’s condition evokes feelings of inadequacy, that one’s affective condition is inappropriate or even incoherent.


Slide from the presentation by Isern-Mas

 

Carme Isern-Mas presented on "The Affective Injustice of therapy Speak". Although therapy speak is not properly analysed in philosophy, it is an important phenomenon to study in relation to epistemic injustice because it can be seen to promote both epistemic and affective injustice. Carme used some interesting examples to how how therapy speak can be weaponised, including the case of Jonah Hill who talked about 'boundaries' to control his partner's behaviour, or the case of a boss sending employees on a 'wellbeing' course to deal with burn-out caused by the stress in the workplace.

Obviously, therapy speak isn't always a bad thing and it can even help overcome epistemic injustice, challenge stigma around mental health, and help identity new phenomena. However, it can be misapplied, and lead to over-simplification, trivialisation, dilution of meaning, pathologization, and inappropriate self-diagnosis. As a consequence, people using therapy speak can discredit the testimony of others for no good reason, evade responsibility for their behaviour, signal that their status is privileged, and give to an impartial observer the impression that they are adopting an objective stance.

Therapy speak also exploits the authority of medical advice, conflates descriptive and normative terms, hides normative claims, and provides to the person who uses it the opportunity to merely deny the other person's perspective on the basis of this more "scientific" and "objective" stance that however may have no medical justification and a very vague relationship with the concepts actually used by therapists.

Therapy speak also perpetuates affective injustice by contributing to deny uptake for the other person's testimony, silencing different perspectives or objections to the "medicalised" interpretation of the situation, testimonial smothering, perpetuating the claim that the other person suffers from a credibility deficit and demanding that the listener (who may be the oppressed member of the group) regulate their own emotions in line with the speaker's interpretation. On a broader scale, it may also result into an example of emotional imperialism.


Day one speakers!


Day two speakers!


Wednesday, 25 September 2024

Understanding Oneself through Others Day 1

Winterbourne House and Garden

This is a report by Jodie Russell. On 23rd and 24th September Eleanor Byrne and Kathleen Murphy-Hollies organised a workshop at the University of Birmingham, bringing together researchers interested in the area of the intersection of epistemic injustice and distributed cognition. The venue for the workshop was the beautiful Winterbourne House and Garden. 

On day one, postdoctoral researchers on EPIC Kathleen Murphy-Hollies, Eleanor Byrne, and Jodie Russell and EPIC project partner Michael Larkin introduced project EPIC and talked about their research to date. Kathleen is interested in how our self concepts and our relationships with others shape our identities. Eleanor is working on affective injustice, a type of injustice that relates to how a persons’s emotions are given (or denied) uptake by others. Jodie aims to establish an intersectional, feminist approach to psychiatry. Michael is going to work with the EPIC Birmingham team to develop a case study on epistemic injustice in young people with psychosis and his own research is about the importance on relationships for youth mental health.


Some key information about project EPIC


Our first speaker was our keynote Allan Køster from the Danish National Centre for Grief with a talk titled "Consolation: a fundamental existential category". Køster made the case for a new understanding of the phenomena of consolation to better capture how it relates to grief and loss. 


Slide from Køster's presentation


Køster noted, for example, that doctors are often faced with instances where they must inform a terminally ill patient of their prognosis. In such cases, there is little hope the doctor can offer the patient which raises the question of how we are to face such situations when inevitable and where little comfort can be offered. 

This is where we often turn to the practice of consolation, but what consolation is, is not yet clear. 
Køster thus presented an existential account of consolation based on the work of Heidegger. On this account, life is felt to be overwhelmingly burdensome, and this isn’t something we live in spite of, but, instead, it’s a fundamental aspect of our existence. 

Consolation should then be seen as, according to Køster, the attempt to unburden oneself or another from the weight of existence. This can be achieved through a kind of “delegating” or distributing the weight of that burden onto the world and others. For example, when we feel consoled by a walk through nature, part of the burden of existence is offloaded onto our environment. 

Our next presentation was given by Zuzanna Rucińska from the University of Antwerp. Her talk was titled "Understanding suicidality as a situated phenomenon" and focused on the cognitive and affective scaffolding of individuals with suicidal ideation. 

Rucińska began by presenting a puzzle around suicidality; individuals who experience suicidal thoughts are often ambivalent about life. Rucińska noted that in attempting to takes one’s own life, individuals often change their mind in the act. There is, nevertheless, for many individuals, an authentic desire to die that can come and go over a lifetime. Given this ambivalence, the question is raised as to why some people attempt to end their lives. 


Rucińska's presentation


Rucińska then proposed to answer this question through providing an account based on the interplay of the individual and her situation. Rucińska noted, for instance, the significance of the method of suicide; individuals do not change methods when their preferred method isn’t available, and studies on the restriction of particular products which are used in culturally preferred methods of suicide showed a reduction in suicide mortality. 

From this, Rucińska suggested that the environment can afford for suicidal actions; a suicidal person will perceive and attend to the features of her environment that will assist her in taking her life. These are features others might not necessarily notice due to our individual histories which have shaped how spaces are meaningful to us in specific ways. Moreover, the desire to die and to live are not contradictory but reflect the very dynamic relationship all individuals have with the environment where, for the suicidal, the opportunity to take one’s life might appear and recede as they navigate the world. 

Rucińska’s analysis implies further that a different environment will afford for different actions. Therefore, on a situated view, not only do we better understand the phenomenology of suicidality but this also potentially opens up new avenues for suicide prevention. 

After a hearty lunch break, our morning session was followed up by an interesting talk by Zamir Kadodia from the University of Exeter on a joint project with Joel Krueger on "Epistemic Injustice, Niche Construction & Neurodiversity".  

Kadodia introduced the neurodiversity paradigm from which their critique stems. This paradigm characterises neurodiversity as cognitive difference and states that the idea of a “healthy” or “normal” brain or mind is a construction. This is in contrast to the pathology paradigm which has characterised neurodiversity as disorder.  

According to the neurodiversity paradigm, neurodivergent individuals, such as those that are autistic, should be considered as a minority group. This is especially important to consider, Kadodia notes, as neurodivergent voices have been historically excluded from attempts to understand neurodivergence itself.

Kadodia and Krueger’s goal, however, is to highlight more surreptitious forms of marginalisation experienced by neurodivergent individuals. Kadodia discussed here an example from Miranda Fricker; in this case, an individual mistakes a shy person for being insincere because their shy behaviour (e.g. avoiding eye contact) makes the individual appear to be untrustworthy. Fricker counts this as a case of bad luck, not epistemic injustice, but Kadodia argued that this case looks different when we swap in the shy person for an autistic person. 


Slide in Kadodia's presentation


In this new example, Kadodia argued that this is a case of epistemic injustice because the neurodivergent person is being judged by norms of trustworthy behaviour that are determined and enacted by neurotypical individuals. As marginalised individuals, neurodivergent people don’t get to contribute to these epistemic norms, but are nevertheless expected to conform to them. This is worrisome because it means that norms of communication for neurodivergent individuals are given less credibility, which leads to a "neurotype identity prejudice", meaning that neurodivergent needs are neglected or, in the worst cases, stigmatised. 

Kadodia then problematised this further by translating this discussion around neurotypical norms to the framework of niche construction, arguing that stereotypes about neurodivergent people in the social imagination become entrenched in material practices, e.g. habits and interactions with the physical and social environment, just as neurotypical norms also become part of the habitual and embodied ways of being in the world.  

Kadodia thus called for the need for neurodiversification, which entails a greater representation of neurotypes and even a clash between different norms in order to facilitate a constructive conversation over the niches we live in. 


Slide from Latham's presentation


Afterwards, Sally Latham from Birmingham Metropolitan College talked to us about "Why self-help is not always helpful". Latham began with some self-help examples in popular culture we are all too familiar with, for instance, the idea of changing how you think in order to transform your situation. 

Latham made the case that much pop culture self-help emphasise a narrative of personal responsibility and individual choice; it is through our own efforts, these narratives suggest, that we will overcome our circumstances. However, drawing on Frank and Foucault, Latham argued that these narratives perpetuate a "ruse of liberation". This is achieved through technologies of the self, what are techniques used to understand oneself and even transform oneself.  

These technologies themselves can be used to control individuals through self-monitoring. In this way, Latham compared self-help to the panopticon; it becomes a way through which to constantly monitor and measure our 'selves' through the various exercises self-help prescribes. Self-help is given normative force for this purpose from its proximity to psychology and the authority of wellbeing 'experts'.  

The flip side of this, Latham described, is that reactions to negative life events that don't follow the positive, self-actualising framework of self-help become taboo. This is tantamount to epistemic injustice by excluding particular social experiences, which marginalises individuals who cannot face, e.g., illness with positivity. Due to the focus on individual responsibility, this may also lead to the blaming of vulnerable people for their negative outlook on life. Latham proposed, as one solution, that we should change the definition of self-help itself so that it might be more fruitful in future. 

Lastly, presented in a hybrid format, Lucy Osler (Cardiff University) and Louise Richardson-Self (University of Tasmania) closed the first day of the workshop with the talk “It Just Goes to Show That You Actually Need to Listen to Your Patients Sometimes: Distributed Cognition, Epistemic Injustice, and the (Under)diagnosis of Endometriosis".

Slide from Osler and Richardson-Self's presentation


Osler and Richardson started by informing us on some statistics on endometriosis. Shockingly, 1 in 7 people assigned female at birth are diagnosed, and diagnosis can take more than 8 years in the UK. The consequences of a delayed diagnosis involve a range of physical and social harms. Osler and Richardson, however, were focussing on epistemic and affective harms. 

They argued that there are persistent, systematic identity-tracking prejudices within wider western healthcare practices. In particular, women experience disproportionate levels of bias in diagnosis and treatment of health conditions. Richardson noted further that the level of confidence gynaecologist and women’s health GP’s have in their skills in managing patients with chronic pelvic pain is worryingly low. Moreover, gynaecologists report that they are not likely to consider patient beliefs and goals in regards to managing chronic pelvic pain.

Not only can this lead to physical and social harms, patients with endometriosis also suffer epistemic and affective harms as their testimony is overlooked or discredited. These patients are thus left with feelings of self-doubt, abandonment, shame, and mistrust of the medical establishment. This raises the question of what features enable the dynamic between medical practitioner and patient to play out in ways that perpetuate epistemic harms in the case of endometriosis.

Osler framed this issue in terms of niche construction and scaffolding; medical knowledge is often distributed among healthcare professionals, medical tools and textbooks which come together to form the niche of western healthcare. The underdiagnosis of endometriosis in women can be understood, Osler argued, in terms of the failure of this medical niche to epistemically support those with endometriosis. 

Rounding off their talk, Richardson and Osler then introduced the symbol of the “Endo Warrior” as a form of resistance of epistemic injustice through empowerment. The use of social media is critical this process as a safe space and efficient medium for sharing expertise and experience.

This talk closed the first day of the workshop. Next week we will report from the second day of the workshop. Watch this space!