In this post, project EPIC postdoc Jodie Russell summarises her recent paper “Psychiatry as Mind-shaping”, published in Erkenntnis:
I make the case that researchers in mental health, clinicians and the wider public participate in a process called mind-shaping. By highlighting the involvement of these individuals in shaping the minds of people with disordered experiences, we can better understand phenomena like looping effects (when the behaviour of the person being labelled changes in response to that label, which in turn changes the meaning of the label). Moreover, characterising psychiatry as mind-shaping also helps us understand harms like epistemic injustice in a new light. But, first, let me unpack what I mean by psychiatry as mind-shaping.
Mind-shaping is a particular theory of social cognition – the study of how we understand each other. In contrast to traditional theories of social cognition, where we try to ‘read’ the minds of other people, the mind-shaping thesis proposes that understanding occurs through trying to get another person to conform to some set of shared rules. For example, I understand that my partner is hungry because their behaviour conforms to certain norms of being a ‘hungry person’, i.e., they rub their stomach, look wistfully at the kitchen, or graze on near-by biscuits. In this example, I try to understand what ‘type’ of person my partner is trying to be, assuming their behaviour conforms to some norms of that ‘type’ that I also adhere to.
In this way, I argue that researchers and clinicians are trying
to understand what kinds of people individuals with disordered experiences are.
In other words, clinicians and researchers might try and understand whether
someone is a ‘well’ or ‘unwell’ person, a person with schizophrenia, or a
person with a brain disease etc.
However, under the mind-shaping view, this process of
categorizing people comes with certain expectations; in order for social
understanding to be successful, it may be necessary to conform to
certain norms. For example, for my partner and I to successfully coordinate
over our shared task of making food for dinner, I really need to know that my
partner is hungry. If they act hungry when they aren’t, we’ll make food for no
reason. If they don’t act hungry when they are, my partner starves (if they are
feeling melodramatic). Either way, if my partner is unreliable in conforming to
norms, it makes working together to make dinner more difficult, and
communication in general might struggle if they are not in some way reliable.
There are therefore certain expectations at play in social understanding; if
you are a hungry person, you should act like it. This is what it means to be
mind-shaped.
This has, however, some unintended consequences when it
comes to mental health research, namely, that individuals with mental disorder
who are labelled may be prone to particular “expectancy effects”. In other
words, by being labelled or studied in a particular way, as a particular kind
of person, people with mental disorder may be obligated to act in certain ways.
One such case study of this can be seen in a study conducted by Örmonet al. (2014). They noticed that the women in their study who had experienced
abuse did not often have their experiences validated by clinicians, with their history
of abuse considered irrelevant to diagnosis, and thus the women did not receive
what they felt was the appropriate care. As such, the women responded to this
treatment by changing their behaviour to conform to particular disorder categories
that were seen as worthy of care (such as bipolar disorder). In this case, I
argue that the women conformed to norms of being mentally unwell that
clinicians typically expected to find; by understanding their patients as
unwell, the clinicians were then able to provide some kind of care for these
women. In this way, both the patients and clinicians were mind-shaped in order
to coordinate on some goal (getting care for the women).
The consequences of this particular case study, however, was
that the struggle of the women to have their abuse acknowledged was then interpreted
by clinical staff through the lens of mental illness. This struggle was then either
a mental health problem or secondary to the mental health problem. It is in
this way that I think we should pay closer attention to the effects of
mind-shaping, and how it may perpetuate epistemic injustices. Given that a core
part of social understanding is the expectation we conform to shared norms, we
may not only present very narrow options to individuals with mental disorder if
they want to be understood by others (e.g. through the lens of specific
disorder categories that may or may not fit their experiences), we may also
exclude as irrelevant, or un-understandable, those behaviours, thoughts and
feelings, which don’t fit our expectations but that are nevertheless important to
the individual in question. The solution, I would want to propose, is giving
people with mental disorder more agency to determine what norms are in play so
that they might be better understood on their own terms.
No comments:
Post a Comment
All comments are moderated.