Showing posts with label epistemic harms. Show all posts
Showing posts with label epistemic harms. Show all posts

Wednesday, 6 August 2025

Toxic Positivity and Epistemic Injustice

 

The words 'positive vibes only' in colourful letters


Toxic positivity (TP) is “the phenomenon of people being positive and optimistic to a degree that is unreasonable in a given situation, and as such makes others feel as if their own (less than positive) feelings are invalid or in some way wrong, thus having the potential to cause harm to the victim” (de Rijk 2025). For example, if one loses a loved one and tries to garner support from a friend who then tells you that you should not be sad because your loved one is in a better place, you may have fallen victim to TP. 

Features of  Toxic Positivity

TP has four features: 

1) appropriate emotion in the victim as a starting point

2) unreasonable optimism on the part of the perpetrator

3) dismissal of the victim 

4) potential harm to the victim 




A woman curled up on the floor with a yellow sun behind her head. Her face is hidden by her hair.



Toxic Positivity and Epistemic Injustice

I have argued (de Rijk 2025) that TP is an epistemic injustice because it has the potential to undermine knowledge to which the victim ought to have a claim so wronging the victim as a knower (Fricker 2007). Further, this is a particularly sneaky kind of epistemic injustice because it often masquerades as something good, because optimism is seldom considered problematic. Knowledge might be undermined through TP in at least three ways, all of which have their root in the doubt-instigation that is caused through dismissal. 

First, TP can make a victim doubt their belief and genuinely doubting a belief means that it can no longer count as knowledge. Second, TP could make a victim lose their belief because they might think the best course of action in response to genuinely doubting their belief. Thirdly, a victim may lose self-trust, which is a precondition for acquiring and maintaining knowledge (e.g., Zagzebski 2012; Dormandy 2024), although this would only happen in the most serious cases. 



A smiley-face emoji and sad-face emoji.



Toxic Positivity and Getting Proper Medical Help

I now argue that TP that undermines knowledge formed through negative emotional experiences related to health can prevent one from timeously seeking proper healthcare. Imagine you are suffering a serious bout of depression but remain highly functional. You confide in a friend that you think you are depressed and need help. But your friend responds by pointing out that you do not seem depressed, you are going about your life as normal and even cracking jokes with your friends and colleagues, he suggests that maybe you are just feeling stressed about an upcoming deadline and when it has passed you will feel better. 


This makes some sense to you, and you begin to seriously doubt that you really are depressed even though you continue to feel all the symptoms of depression. Nonetheless, the doubt sown by TP acts as a defeater to your belief that you are depressed. 



A woman removes a happy mask to reveal her sad face.


So, you do not seek proper treatment for your depression (because why should you seek treatment if you are not really depressed?) and eventually suffer a complete nervous breakdown. In this case, TP has prevented you from seeking timeous medical help and as a result you ended up in a far worse position than you might otherwise have been.

This is just one way that TP undermining knowledge in connection with our health can prevent one seeking healthcare. But it is sufficient to show that undermining knowledge formed through negative emotions related to health can be detrimental to taking the right steps to ensure that one receives proper medical help before one’s condition worsens. 


Headshot of Shené de Rijk
Shené de Rijk is a PhD candidate at the University of Johannesburg in South Africa. She is affiliated with the African Centre for Epistemology and Philosophy of Science (ACEPS). Her dissertation is centred on investigating the phenomenon of toxic positivity in the field of social epistemology. Other than toxic positivity and social epistemology (and epistemic injustice in particular), her research interests include applied ethics, especially bioethics on which she has also written.



Wednesday, 29 January 2025

Workshop report: Loneliness, Metaphor & Empathy

Last week, Project EPIC held a workshop at the University of Nottingham entitled 'Loneliness, Metaphor & Empathy'. This workshop featured three talks by Project EPIC postdocs Fred Cooper (Bristol), Kathleen Murphy-Hollies (Birmingham) and Eleanor Byrne (Nottingham). 

The workshop theme reflects some current research interests of the project postdocs. All three talks teased out varieties of epistemic injustice that can arise when certain forms of suffering are marginalised by others. Fred asked what epistemic injustices might be at stake in claiming that certain experiences are inherently unknowable, Kathleen discussed the role of various prejudices in shaping how uptake-worthy we take people's claims to be, and Eleanor discussed the extent to which attempts to empathise with others can result in epistemic injustices.

Fred began the day with his talk The Naked Terror: Joseph Conrad, 'True Loneliness' and the inability to know. Fred discussed themes of loneliness in Conrad's Under Western Eyes where there is an implication that loneliness--or rather, 'true loneliness'--is characteristically unknowable. He gives us the following quote:

Who knows what true loneliness is-not the conventional word, but the naked terror? To the lonely themselves it wears a mask. The most miserable outcast hugs some memory or some illusion. Now and then a fatal conjunction of events may lift the veil for an instant. For an instant only. No human being could bear a steady view of moral solitude without going mad. 

Fred Cooper

Fred argued for a closer historical interrogation of the ways that epistemically  unjust or constraining narratives on health and ilness are sustained over time.

Kathleen then talked about metaphorical meaning and giving 'uptake' to the experiences of people with delusions and various other false beliefs. She argued argued that the content of what people say is often over-scrutinised for accuracy and truth, and that these tendencies are often exacerbated by prejudices.

Kathleen Murphy-Hollies

For example, she mentions how the claims of asylum seekers are often over-scrutinised for truth and accuracy as a result of certain prejudices. Ultimately, Kathleen's position is that even when we highly doubt that a certain belief expressed is true, there are still possible meanings to give uptake to in our engagement with them. Kathleen argued that dismissing those meanings can constitute a form of epistemic injustice, and that giving uptake to metaphorical meaning is a way of engaging with the agents' best attempts to communicate their experiences.

Some members of Project EPIC (L>R; Alice Monypenny; Fred Cooper; Ian James Kidd; Eleanor Byrne; Kathleen Murphy-Hollies)

Eleanor Byrne then closed the day with her talk about empathy. Drawing on ongoing collaborative work with Allan Køster (Danish National Centre for Grief), Eleanor discussed the limits of empathic understanding in contexts of profound suffering. She engaged with recent critiques of empathy which state that certain experiences are too alien, too profoundly catastrophic, to be understood by others. She concedes that some experiences can evade understanding, but maintains that some basic form of empathy remains possible no matter the circumstances at hand. This, she called ground empathy. 

Eleanor drew on a passage by Georg Simmel in order to argue that no matter the profound difference in your circumstances, it is always possible to empathically relate to the other person by attending to the fact that we all share the same existential fragility. Simmel writes:

All the thoughts and fates that make us suffer are actually only the occasional causes that bring about a part of the infinite potential for suffering that is inherent in us. [...] The most uncanny thing is that on such occasions we get the inkling of an immeasurable store of suffering that we carry around with us as if in a sealed vessel; a dark being that is not yet reality, but is still there somewhere, from which fate always releases certain parts, but leaves behind an inexhaustible amount. Most of the time this vessel rumbles quite quietly within us, but sometimes, when a single misery or shock opens it, it starts to move, to tremble dully, and we feel – we ourselves do not know where or what it means – this terrible treasure of potential suffering that we carry around with us that is our dowry, which can never be fully realised, cannot be exhausted by any real misery.


(Simmel 1923, Fragmente und Aufsätze)

Eleanor takes this passage to be illustrative of the inherent fragility that lies within all of us, waiting to be made salient by misfortune. It is by attending to these facts of life, the contingency of our position, that we are able to empathically relate to (if not understand) others in times of catastrophic upheaval, illness and suffering. 

This was the first official Nottingham event for Project EPIC. Keep an eye out for updates and adverts for upcoming events across Nottingham, Bristol and Birmingham.



Wednesday, 24 April 2024

Epistemic Microaggressions in Healthcare

In its relatively short history, the growing literature on epistemic injustice in healthcare has come a long way in highlighting the distinctly epistemic dimensions of medical encounters that can lead to a variety of injustices for patients. Such injustices are often the result of differences in relationships of institutional, professional, and social power (Kidd and Carel 2017, Freeman and Stewart 2024, Stewart and Freeman, 2022). 

This literature is mostly focused on how phenomena such as testimonial injustice and hermeneutical injustice render patients epistemically vulnerable. Additionally, it has helped to illuminate some of the ways in which patients from marginalized groups have their epistemic agency constrained, undermined, or ignored as they attempt to make claims about their bodies, identities, or health status to healthcare professionals. However, this literature has only recently started to attend to some of the more subtle, covert, and insidious mechanisms of epistemic dismissal.
 
In our recently published book, Microaggressions in Medicine, we engage with some of these seemingly subtler forms of epistemic (and other) types of injustice and harm in medical contexts. Let’s zoom out to mention the overall aims and goals of the book before zooming back in to focus on the epistemic dimensions of these injustices.

The two main theoretical aims of Microaggressions in Medicine are to reconceptualize how microaggressions have been understood by psychologists and philosophers and to introduce a new conceptualization of microaggressions that we call a harm-based account. 

Our harm-based account categorizes microaggressions according to the kind of harm that results for those who experience them. As such, we propose and argue for the following three kinds of microaggressions: epistemic microaggressions that result in epistemic harm, emotional microaggressions that result in emotional harm, and self-identity microaggressions that result in harms to one’s sense of self.


Microaggressions in Medicine (2024)


There are three applied aims of the book. 
  • Using first-personal narratives, case studies, and testimonies of patients who are members of marginalized groups, we develop this harm-based account within medical contexts. 
  • Analyzing these case studies, we illuminate the serious and enduring harms of microaggressions and argue that they can ultimately lead to delaying or avoiding medical care, damaged trust relations with healthcare professionals, and ultimately worse health outcomes for patients who experience them. 
  • We introduce practical tools and strategies to help healthcare professionals reduce microaggressions in their practices and institutions, thereby diminishing harm caused to patients.

In what follows, and drawing on chapter 4 of the book, we focus on epistemic microaggressions, epistemic harm, and discuss why attending to epistemic microaggressions is an important part of the larger picture of epistemic injustice in healthcare.

In medical contexts, epistemic microaggressions are intentional or unintentional verbal or gestural slights made by healthcare professionals that dismiss, ignore, or otherwise fail to recognize claims that patients make about their bodies or health. Epistemic microaggressions result in epistemic harm to recipients (here, patients), namely, harm to them in their capacity as knowers. 

One example of an epistemic microaggression that we develop in the book is the story of what happened to the famous sociologist, professor, writer, and MacArthur “genius” award winner, Tressie McMillan Cottom. Despite her social standing and countless intellectual and academic achievements, as a self-described fat, Black (and at the time, pregnant) woman, Cottom knew that given her identity, she would face an array of discriminations. For this reason, she carefully chose her physicians. Or so she thought.

When she was four months pregnant, bleeding and experiencing acute pain, Cottom knew that something was terribly wrong. Yet when she and her then husband arrived at her doctor’s office, instead of being seen immediately or being sent directly to the emergency department, she was told to sit patiently in the waiting room. When she finally got to see her doctor, he looked at her and quickly said that she was probably just too fat and that for “women like her,” spotting was typical at this stage of pregnancy. She was sent home.

When, later that night, her pain escalated, the on-call nurse assured her over the phone that because the pain was in her bowel and not her lower back, that it was probably constipation and that she should try to go to the bathroom. After three days of such pain and no sleep, Cottom went to the hospital, where she was told that she’d probably just eaten something that was “bad” for her. 

After insisting that she get an ultrasound, it showed the fetus, in addition to two large tumors. Upon seeing this, the nurse scolded Cottom: “You should have said something” (Cottom 2019, 84). Soon thereafter, Cottom went into early labor. She gave birth to her daughter, who died soon after she was born (ibid., 85). While making plans for how to handle her daughter’s remains, another nurse said: “Just so you know, there was nothing we could have done since you never told us that you were in labor” (ibid.).

There are countless microaggressive harms that Cottom experienced. It’s important to underscore however, that the result of those microaggressions was nothing micro. Our analysis focuses on how racialized and gendered epistemic microaggressions combine in ways that are unique to Black women (what we call the misogynoir of microaggressions).

In this case, it was clear that Cottom knew that there was something wrong, tried to convey this knowledge to her healthcare team, and continued to be viewed as lacking credibility with regards to her knowledge of her body. As a result of the entrenched biases and stereotypes about Black women, Cottom experienced a panoply of racialized gendered epistemic microaggressions. 

As a pregnant Black woman who was bleeding and in pain, her bleeding was attributed to her fatness. Then, her pain in her bowel was dismissed as being the consequences of something “bad” that she’d eaten, where “bad” has racist undertones about the kinds of food that Black people eat. Finally, after the death of her newborn daughter, she was blamed for not having spoken up sooner, with the implication that the death was in part her fault and could have been prevented had she spoken up.

Cottom is powerless relative to the healthcare professionals.

Her knowledge of her body is ignored.

Repeatedly, healthcare professionals assumed they knew better.

On account of her race, gender, and body size, Cottom suffered the epistemic harm of not being recognized as a credible knower, the practical harms of severe physical pain, the death of her daughter, as well as the enduring trauma of the whole experience.

These consequences are macro and tragic. But we are most concerned with the epistemic racialized gendered microaggressions that contributed to them. Cottom’s credibility as a knower was denied due to her race, gender, and body size and as a result, her knowledge claims were ignored or dismissed.

The racialized gendered epistemic microaggressions that Cottom experienced are reflections of imbalances in epistemic and other sorts of social power that themselves mirror broader patterns at play both within and beyond healthcare contexts. Healthcare workers belong to an elite professional class. They’re assumed to have epistemic authority within and beyond that context. They often exert epistemic power over their patients by blocking them from making meaningful contributions to clinical exchanges. This epistemic situation both reflects and reifies assumptions about power in the epistemic domain. For example, it makes clear who creates, controls, and deploys knowledge and who doesn’t; who is “rational” or “objective” and who isn’t (cf. Code 1991).

The epistemic microaggressions on which we have focused, combined with more macro and explicit stereotypes and assumptions about Black women, result in epistemic harms to patients: they’re denied the full status of knower, which is central to human dignity and value (Fricker 2007; Pohlhaus Jr. 2017; Dotson 2011). 

Because the epistemic contributions of patients who are members of marginalized groups are routinely blocked, over time this can result in patients coming to doubt their own epistemic capacities, especially as microaggressions add up and their harms accumulate (Evans and Mallon 2020). As we saw and as we develop further in our book, epistemic microaggressions can also lead to harmful health and other consequences.

As Cottom’s case makes clear, epistemic microaggressions are harmful to the epistemic status and agency of marginalized patients. A complete understanding of epistemic justice and injustice in healthcare and the myriad ways they manifest must include attention to the subtle epistemic dismissals and indignities that epistemic microaggressions reflect.



Heather Stewart is Assistant Professor of
Philosophy at Oklahoma State University.
Lauren Freeman is a Professor of 
Philosophy at University of Louisville.

Wednesday, 17 January 2024

Epistemic Injustice: Caution and Complexity

Epistemic injustice has become a ‘hot topic’ in philosophy since the 2007 publication of Miranda Fricker’s book. Project EPIC is one product of the now-enormous field of epistemic injustice studies, which extends into other academic disciplines. This industry and interest, while welcome, brings with it the usual hazards of concepts that ‘go viral’. Over time, rich concepts are reduced to slogans or single-sentence definitions. A specific vocabulary becomes widespread but decoupled from its underlying theoretical machinery (think of Kuhn on ‘paradigm shifts’).

Academic fashions are unavoidable, as are trade-offs, such as that between the complexity and the communicability of a concept. Conceptual uptake is to be encouraged where it is productive: we should not want to lock ourselves into our specialist silos. Moreover, good work can often be done with simple versions of complicated concepts. The challenge is to use concepts, like epistemic injustice, while also maintaining sensitivity to complexity, detail, and nuance.





With that in mind, here are some problematic tendencies to note in epistemic injustice studies:

  1. the tendency to use the term ‘epistemic injustice’ in over-generalised ways to mean ‘anything epistemically bad’. Granted, epistemic injustices are heterogenous, but there are lots of epistemically bad things in the world. Not all of them are epistemic injustices. Other normative concepts and evaluative vocabularies are available, which may better fit different cases. Defaulting to epistemic injustice might obscure the normative details of certain cases. We must use the right concepts for the task at hand, not just the ones we are have become accustomed to using.
  2. a tendency to use overly simplistic accounts of the nature, causes, harms, and wrongs of epistemic injustice. Negative stereotypes, for instance, are a cause of testimonial injustice, but not the only one. Stereotype-centred accounts are sometimes right for the case at hand, but if used carelessly can disguise the many causes of epistemic injustices. Similarly, while many hermeneutical injustices fit Fricker’s original account of the lack of relevant interpretive resources, others involve the presence of distorting resources. Other cases will involve both lacks and presences of different kinds of resources. These sorts of distinctions are vital to capturing the particularity of different cases.
  3. a tendency to rely on under-articulated accounts of epistemic injustice. It is now standard to define an epistemic injustice as ‘a wrong done to someone specifically in their capacity as a knower’. However, this gloss sets up complicated questions – about the nature of the wrong, for instance, or what it means to be a knower. Sometimes, a gloss is enough, but there are many cases where the detail really matters. Many details of Fricker’s original account are not taken up, including in cases where they would help (such as the idea of ‘economies of credibility’ or her virtue-epistemological framing of testimonial justice).
  4. a tendency to default to the original 2007 Frickerian framework without considering its subsequent amendments (such as the idea of structural testimonial injustice) or criticisms of the original Frickerian account or the alternative forms of epistemic injustice (such as contributory injustice) offered by other scholars. Granted, the epistemic injustice studies scholarship is enormous, and, if the original account will do the work, that’s fine. But there is much more in epistemic injustice studies than the 2007 book.

In describing these four tendencies, I am not impugning work in epistemic injustice studies. The tendencies indicate hazards to recognise and avoid. 

Here are some others, including problems particular to studies of epistemic injustice in relation to illness and healthcare:

  • Doctor-bashing. Epistemic injustice within healthcare is a clear problem and there are important criticisms to make of healthcare systems. However, there is a temptation to put the concept in the service of ‘doctor-bashing’. Sometimes, individual healthcare practitioners are at fault. Even where they are, though, there can be complex causes, many involving major structural problems of healthcare systems like the NHS. Rushing to ‘bash’ individuals risks obscuring the messy personal, interpersonal, and institutional realities of healthcare practice.
  • ‘Grab-bag’ approaches. Epistemic injustice as a concept clearly resonates with many people, who are then tempted to ‘grab’ the concept and immediately put it to work. However, using a concept properly means respecting its nuances and the constraints on its use. Contrary to some claims, epistemic injustices can, but need not, be systematic or lead to dehumanization. Over-defining a concept is one consequence of grab-bagging. This is not to say that only trained epistemologists should be allowed to use the concept. But it does mean that concepts, like tools, must be used with due care.
  • Contesting claims. Many people experience epistemic injustices in the course of their lives. As Fricker emphasises, the concept helps those people to recognise and understand these kinds of injustice. However, not everything that one calls an epistemic injustice is an epistemic injustice. One can interpret an encounter as being epistemically unjust when it is not. It is not an epistemic injustice, for instance, if a healthcare practitioner does not automatically believe the patient’s own interpretation of their symptoms. There may be epistemically good reasons for their doing so. Questioning someone’s interpretations of their experiences is not necessarily epistemically unjust. After all, interpretations can be and are appraised – as plausible or implausible, strained or sensible, and so on. Moreover, interpretation is often be a shared task, not something a person does by themselves and then reports to others. Now, contesting claims of epistemic injustice is a delicate task. However, we will need to get better at it as the concept of epistemic injustice becomes more widely used.
  • Lived experience. Epistemic injustice is often used in conjunction with the popular concept of ‘lived experience’. Unfortunately, that term is too often either undefined, underdefined, or defined in banal terms – as, say, ‘experience from the first-person perspective’. Definitional vagary is often accompanied by a tendency to draw further, very contestable epistemological claims. For instance, having ‘lived experience’ is often interpreted as a conferral of expertise. But expertise involves social roles, systems of training and accreditation, and a defined institutional context for one’s conduct. In other cases, ‘lived experience’ is asserted or implied to be something others must accept, as if being epistemic just to someone entails a generalised policy of credulous deference. Epistemic life is too complex for that. It is a matter of contexts, roles, trust and distrust, uncertainty and doubt, – of interaction, discussion, questioning, and delicately structured activities of criticism, affirmation, challenge, clarification, agreement and disagreement. We ignore all this by taking epistemic justice to involve little more than nodding along to whatever one hears.

These tendencies and challenges can all be resisted. It is perfectly possible to use the rich conceptual resources of epistemic injustice studies in ways that honour the moral and epistemic complexities of life. In the case of healthcare, such carefulness matters all the more. Much good work remains to be done – if one is careful, rigorous, and respectful of the messy complexity of our concepts and, indeed, our lives.


This post is by Ian James Kidd
Kidd is associate professor in the Department of Philosophy at the University of Nottingham and investigator in project EPIC. Kidd has a variety of research interests, including phenomenology, epistemology, feminist philosophy, and the philosophy of healthcare.


Wednesday, 20 December 2023

Reflections on trauma

On November 29th, 2023, the EPIC project and the Bristol Centre for Health Humanities and Science (CHHS) convened a multidisciplinary, collaborative workshop involving health practitioners, academic researchers, and students to explore lived experiences of trauma. 

More specifically, the workshop delved into trauma as experienced by clinicians, their patients, and marginalized or vulnerable societal groups, including children, women, and people from socioeconomically disadvantaged populations. To explore these experiences, we were joined by five speakers with expertise in trauma-related research.



In a timely talk exploring childhood trauma, Dr. Maya Mukamel explained how the ambiguous legal and political status of children in some countries renders them susceptible to human rights violations and various moral and epistemic harms. 

This was followed by an exploration of post-traumatic stress disorder (PTSD) in Virginia Woolf’s Mrs. Dalloway, where Dr. Lizzie Gourd highlighted the trauma that can occur during and in the aftermath of war. This fuelled discussion about post-World War II Britain, characterized by enduring scars and a ‘wilful determination for closure.’

Other talks explored how trauma is encountered in healthcare and medical education. In a talk titled ‘The Healing Paradox,’ Dr. Louise Younie explored the role of 'creative inquiry' using artistic practices to equip clinicians with conceptual tools for navigating emotional complexities. She also cautioned against resilience-focused medical discourses, which might inadvertently lead to perfectionism as well as feelings of shame and inadequacy. Alternatively, Dr. Younie proposed an approach centred around ‘flourishing’ and finding creative pathways to integrate trauma-informed care into mainstream medical education.

Echoing these ideas, Dr. Jonathon Tomlinson also stressed the significance of embracing holistic patient perspectives, with greater consideration for intersectionality, lived experience and personal histories. Building on this, he explained that trauma typically escapes diagnosis, manifesting in various chronic and acute illnesses, posing challenges for patients.

Concluding the sessions, Kate Binnie, a music therapist, PhD student, and palliative care practitioner, described the relationship between lived experiences involving breathlessness, trauma, and epistemic injustice. In particular, Kate explained how a body-mind approach, employing song and breathwork practices, can help alleviate potentially traumatic experiences of breathlessness for individuals approaching the end of life.

Collectively, these discussions underscored the interconnectedness of trauma and epistemic injustice, particularly how interactions with clinicians can either alleviate or exacerbate trauma. The speakers unanimously emphasised the need for shared concepts and practices to address trauma experiences, benefiting both healthcare practitioners and their patients.


This post was authored by Kathryn Body, a PhD student in the Department of Philosophy, at the University of Bristol. 

Her research is founded on a multidisciplinary approach, combining insights from social anthropology and phenomenology to qualitatively analyse survey data focused on lived experiences of the Covid-19 pandemic in the UK, Japan, and Mexico. 


Kathryn uses embodied frameworks to create better understanding of the ways people’s relationship with their bodies, other people, and their environment changes during infectious disease outbreaks. She is also a graduate teacher, postgraduate representative, and administrator at the University of Bristol’s Centre of Health Humanities and Science (CHHS).